Supersized Mind

Picture: walker. I was agreeably surprised by Andy Clark’s ‘Supersizing the Mind’.  I had assumed it would be a fuller treatment of the themes set out in ‘The Extended Mind’, the paper he wrote with David Chalmers, and which is included in the book as an Appendix. In fact, it ranges more widely and has a number of interesting points to make on the general significance of embodiment and mind extension.  Various flavours of externalism, the doctrine that the mind ain’t in the head, seem to be popular at the moment, but Clark’s philosophical views are clearly just part of a coherent general outlook on cognition.

Early on, Clark contrasts different approaches to the problem of robotic walking. Asimo, Honda’s famous robot, does a pretty impressive job of walking, but achieves it through an awful lot of very carefully controlled mechanical kit. The humanoid shape of the body, apart from giving the robot its anthropomorphic appeal, is treated as more or less an incidental feature. By contrast, Clark cites Collins, Wisse and Ruina on passive dynamic walkers whose design gives them a natural tendency to waddle along with no control system at all.  These machines are far less complex (one walking toy patented by Fallis in 1888 consists entirely of two pieces of cleverly bent wire – I’m going to try making my own later), but they embody a different kind of sophistication.  As always, evolution got there first, and the relatively good levels of energy efficiency achieved by the ambulant human body, in contrast to the energy-guzzling needs of an Asimo-style approach, show that although human walking is more controlled than two pieces of wire, walking has been cunningly built into the design.

All this serves to introduce the idea that form has more importance than we may think, that legs are not just tools strapped on to the bottom of a standard unit.  The example of feeling with a stick is often quoted; when we use a stick to probe the texture and shape of an object, it doesn’t feel as if we’re registering the motion of the stick against our hand, but rather as if we were really feeling with the stick, as though the stick itself had for the moment become a sensory extension, with feeling at the end, not in the handle.

Clark wants to say that this feeling is not an illusion, that the stick, and other extensions we may use, really are incorporated into us temporarily.  He quotes a dystopian vision of Bruce Sterling in which powerful machines are driven by increasingly feeble and senile humans; why instead shouldn’t the combination of feeble human and carefully designed robotics amount instead to a newly invigorated and intelligent person?

Among the most powerful extensions available for human beings is, of course, language. Words are often considered solely as a means of communication, but he makes a convincing case for the conclusion that they actually add massively to our cognitive abilities. He rightly says that the complexity generated by our ability to think about the way we think, or to think of new worlds from which other new worlds can be found, is staggering.

One of the ways our extended cognition helps us to extend ourselves further is by the construction of niches – re-engineering parts of the world to enhance our own performance. Clark here gives a fascinating account of how Elizabethan actors coped with the impossible load imposed on their memories – in those days it was apparently customary for a company to play six different plays a week with few repetitions and entirely new plays arriving at regular intervals.

Key factors were the standard layout of the stage and documents known as ‘plots’, a kind of high-level map of who comes in when and where and does what. These would enable actors to get a quick overall grasp of a new play, and with a script which gave only their own lines and using an over-learned grasp of the dramatic conventions of the day which gave them an in-built knowledge of the sort of thing that could be expected, they were be able to pick up plays and switch from one to another almost on the fly as they went. This is just a particularly striking example of the way we often make things easier for our brains by reducing the epistemic complexity of the environment.  Putting that piece of IKEA furniture together may be tough, but if we take out all the components and lay them out neatly the way they’re shown in the diagram, it actually becomes easier.

Clark draws a useful distinction, in many ways a key point, between three grades of embodiment. In mere embodiment, the body and sense are simply pieces of equipment with which things can be done; in basic embodiment their own feature and dynamics become resources in themselves which the entity in question can exploit. Finally, in the profound embodiment which humans and some other animals, especially primates, have developed, new parts of the world and new uses of parts of the body are constantly discovered and recruited to serve previously unimagined purposes. This capacity to pick up things and make them part of your own mental apparatus might be a defining feature of human cognition and human consciousness.

All this is fine, but we may ask whether it is enough to make us think cognitive extension is anything more than some fancy metaphors about plain old tool use. Clark now goes on to tackle some objections, first those made by Adams and Aizawa, who in a nutshell say that the kind of processes Clark are talking about are just not the right kind of thing to be considered cognitive.  Various grounds are advanced, but the strongest part of the negative case is perhaps the claim that cognitive processes are distinguished by processes involving non-derived representations. In other words, real minds deal in stuff which is inherently meaningful, and the kinds of things Clark is on about, if they deal in meaning at all, do so only because a real brain interprets them them as doing so. This claim clearly rebuts the example of Otto, used by Clark and Chalmers:  Otto, briefly, uses a notebook as a supplementary memory. It’s not memory, or memory-like, Adams and Aizawa would say, because the information in Otto’s brain is live, it means something all on its own, whereas his notebook only means something through the convention of writing and when brains write or read in it.

Clark suggests that meaningfulness, non-derived representations, can perhaps be found independently of brains in some cases. This is highly contentious territory where I think it might actually be more prudent not to go. There’s no need in any case, since he also has the argument that brains frequently use arbitrary, conventional symbols in internal cognitive activities – whenever we use words or numbers to think with. If those processes are cognitive, surely similar ones using external symbols deserve the same recognition. Is there any real difference between someone who visualises a map in memory in order to work out where to go, and someone who looks at the paper equivalent, such that we can dismiss one as not cognitive?

A different challenge comes from Robert Rupert, who proposes that embedded cognition is enough: we can say that cognitive processes are heavily dependent on external props and prompts without having to make the commitments required by extended cognition. The props and prompts may be essential, but that doesn’t mean we have to bring them within the pale of cognition itself – and in fact if we do we may risk losing sight of the thing we set out to study in the first place. If the mind includes all the teeming series of objects we use to help us think clearly, then the science of the mind is going to be more intractable than ever.

This latter objection is easily dealt with, since Clark is not concerned to deny that there is a recognisable, continuing core of cognition in the brain. On the other point, I’m not sure that choosing embedding over extension has any real advantage here: embedding might give us a cleanly delineated target for the study of the mind, but it explicitly does so by narrowing the scope of that study to exclude all the allegedly intractable swarm of prompts and props which help us out. But aren’t the props and prompts an interesting and essential area of study, even if we deny them the status of being truly cognitive? Clark seems to accept that there is no knock-out case for extension rather than embedding, but he claims a number of advantages for the former, notably that it steers us safely away from ‘magic dust’ and the seductive old idea of the inner homunculus, the little man in our head who controls everything.

In a final section, Clark considers two ‘Limits of Embodiment’. The first has to do with Noë’s argument that perception is active; that seeing is like painting. This Strong Sensorimotor model has many virtues in Clark’s eyes: in particular it moves attention away from the vexed issue of qualia and on to skills. In fact, it is associated with the claim that experience is just constituted by the activity of perception, which leaves no ambiguous ineffable inner reality to trouble us, dismissing the menacing hordes of philosophical zombies that qualophiles would unleash on us. The snag, in Clark’s eyes, is ‘hypersensitivity’ – if we take this line at face value we find ourselves saying that only identical people could have identical experiences, and therefore that no actual people see the same things.

The other limit has to do with an argument that if embodiment is true, functionalism must be false. It is a basic claim of functionalism, after all, that the substrate doesn’t matter; that in principle you could make a brain out of anything so long as it had the right functional properties at a high level. But embodiment says that the nature of the substrate is crucial – so if one is true the other must be false, right? Put as baldly as that, I think the weakness of the argument is apparent; why shouldn’t it be the case that the things which the theory of embodiment says are crucial are in fact, in the final analysis,  functional properties?

The book is a fascinating read, and full of stuff which this short sketch can’t really do any justice to.  I don’t know whether I’ve become a convert to mind extension, though. The problem for me at a philosophical level, is that none of this really worries me.  There are a number of  issues to do with consciousness and the mind where my inability to see the answers is, in a quiet but deep way, quite troubling to me. Cognitive extension,  somehow not so much.

I suppose part of the reason is that lurking at the back of my mind is the feeling that the location of the mind is a false issue. Where is the mind? In some Platonic realm, or zone of abstraction, or perhaps the question is meaningless. When we ask, is the mind within the brain or in the external world , the answer is in fact  ‘No’. Of course I understand that Clark is not operating at this naive level, but it leaves a lingering doubt somewhere at the back of my mind about how much the answer really matters , which is reinforced by the apparent softness of the issue. Clark himself seems to concede that it’s not exactly a question of absolute right and wrong, more of whether this is a useful and enlightening way to look at things. On that level, I certainly found his account convincing.

Perhaps I’ve ended up becoming one of those frivolous people who always want a theory to boggle their minds a bit.

8 thoughts on “Supersized Mind

  1. Fantastic article. As I read your words on my computer screen I would say my mind is extended on the computer screen but being reflected into my brain where I can read and understand it and make my own judgements. I would say my brain and all of its cognitive senses sits in between the outside environment and my body which is the platform or grounding for me.

    Here’s my challenge: Early 20th Century inventions by appropriate American geniuses; internal combustion engine (Henry Ford), airplane (Wright Brothers), phonograph (Thomas Edison), light bulb (Thomas Edison), audion (Lee DeForest) and feedback amplifier (Edwin Armstrong).

    The airplane mimics bird flight but what aspects of biological and human nature do the other inventions mimic?

    What’s the underlying principle for the other inventions?

  2. Hi Peter,
    I’m not quite sure what you mean by “…embodiment says the nature of the substrate is crucial..”

    No doubt, some of the strongest empirical arguments for embodiment derive from cognitive neuroscientific studies, especially having to do with your example of tools being “extensions” of the self in somatosensory cortex. How this self-tool blending is actually computed and deployed seems to not necessarily depend on the nature of neural processing. Similar arguments can be made for the role of the temporo-parietal junction and its role in orienting a representation of the self in space (e.g. transcranial magnetic stimulation on this area has sometime produced feelings of having an out-of-body experience). How does this not comport with the standard picture of having a representation of self and a representation of the environment, etc..I’m similarly worried about arguments made to the effect that focusing on skills (esp. perceptual skills) will somehow bring qualia out of focus. There’s a long loopy journey from raw sense data to transducted percepts to cognitive structure which feeds back to control perception. It’s clear that high-level goals maintained in the prefrontal cortex actively guide perception. If satisfying one of these goals produces some sense of “reward,” it seems that qualia might be involved in guiding attention to goal-salient aspects of the world. I guess I just don’t see it.

    Any clarification is much appeciated.

  3. Mmmm. I chewed over the article for a while trying to get some purchase on the ideas. And then I re-read the penultimate paragraph again and it said, elegantly, what I was struggling to put together.

    I first came across a detailed argument about the ’embodied mind’ in ‘Philosophy in the Flesh’ by Lakoff and Johnson. I thought it was a very refreshing viewpoint – but stretched just a little too far (like many philosophical ideas) to explain too much.

    Is the mind (definition applied for!) embodied. Yes, I think so. The mind is generated from the interactions of various brain processes, the neural system, chemical signals in the body, and the signals from the body’s senses. But in my view the mind is a property of the body (brain, nerves, hormones etc.); the mind has no separate existence from the gubbins that it is embodied in. Sometimes the mind influences and directs the body, but quite often it is just along as a recorder of important bodily events which may be of use in the future.

    When it comes to extension of capability beyond the body’s limits the mind has a function. I think this function is heplping the remainder of the body to ‘learn’ how to map and use the capability. Quite often the extended capability (if practised and habituated) no longer needs the mind. Eg. you don’t need to ‘think’ how to ride a bike, once you have learned. You don’t need to think how to speak, only what to say – and even then some conversation does not need much active thought.

    So in my view arguing about the embodied mind, or the extended mind, is to perpetuate an illusion. I think there may be more merit in discussing the ‘minded body’ or extended action outside the body’s envelope.

    Of course your mileage may vary…

  4. Paul,

    You have to bear in mind that so far as embodiment being contrary to computationalism, is concerned, this is me reporting Clark reporting an argument that neither of us actually agrees with, so it may not be getting the best possible exposition. But as I understand it, that argument is just that if you’re stressing the importance of the physical design, that tends to take you away from thinking that the governing algorithms are all that matters. It’s a bit like Searle’s view that there just is something about neural tissue, something quite understandable but not yet understood, that gives rise to consciousness.

    On qualia I actually believe the argument is weak, although I have sympathy for the conclusion that anything which ran the same functions would necessarily evoke the same phenomenal experience. Not sure I’m really answering your point properly, though.

    DiscoveredJoys – yes, I like ‘minded body’.

  5. Peter,
    Point taken on physical design, although I think it’s a rather weakly argued one on the part of the embodiment folks. Roboticists, AI folks who do evolutionary computation and the lot have shown that ambulation of a virtual (or robotic) entity can be achieved in a wide variety of ways, some of which don’t even involve the thing having a mental representation of its own body. Clearly, humans do have such a representation, and I think that fact is crucial to explain some very odd pathologies of consciousness (among other things), but I’m not at all convinced it matters all that much to mundane skill execution and learning from feedback.

    As for qualia, it seems that having a body-map (or a set of them) that process interoceptive information is part of the story — certainly you’d need such a thing to localise raw sensation. I think I hop off the bus when we get to gedanken experiments about an abacus, and a calculator performing the same (functional) computation and that evoking the same phenomenal experience from the point of view of the calculators. Every brain is wired differently, and almost certainly has different concentrations of calcium, potassium, sodium, GABA, dopamine and so forth. I’m not even sure if those kinds of arguments are worth thinking about unless we can define exactly how senstive each neural computation is to all of these conditioning factors.

  6. Regarding a supposed contradiction between functionalism and embodiment, it is my view that the issue is not properly stated. The problem is that it does not really make sense to ask “where” mind is. It almost does not make sense to talk about “a mind”, certainly not in the sense that a mind is a thing. The mind is surely a property, the behavior of a correctly operating brain. This view is surely compatible with both embodiment and functionalism. It is equally the basis of materialism.

  7. You say “why shouldn’t it be the case that the things which the theory of embodiment says are crucial are in fact, in the final analysis, functional properties?”. Well, in the context of Clark’s ideas this argument is reasonable but Clark has not spotted a basic problem with functionalism:

    “… in the real world, with its non-Alexandrian ontology of physics, invoking “functions” to explain conscious experience leads to an examination of how functions operate. These functions operate as a result of relativistic and quantum physics which in turn require explanations that involve conscious experience. There is an endless loop or “infinite regress” inherent in functionalist explanations of mind in which conscious experience must be invoked to explain the functions that explain conscious experience.” ( Time and conscious experience ).

    My guess is that the problem of conscious observation in physics, especially in Relativity Theory, will probably provide the resolution of the problem of consciousness.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *