Linespace
Onphenes
Linespace

1 April 2006

home 

Riccardo Manzotti

Ted Honderich’s new theory of consciousness – that me being conscious of a room is in some sense just there being a room – was mentioned in these pages a while ago. On that occasion it was noted that, in spite of his philosophical eminence as a former Grote professor, his paper had been rejected by the Journal of Consciousness Studies (not normally a narrow-minded periodical - happy to publish pieces on parapsychology, say or Rupert Sheldrake), and it was suggested that the reason might be that no-one could work out what he was on about. But we liked the rallying-cry with which he ended, calling for further progress.

That call has not gone unanswered. Last August in Copenhagen, at Towards a Science of Consciousness, Honderich, Riccardo Manzotti and Francois Tonneau presented papers in support of their own versions of the theory of Radical Externalism. We could be witnessing the beginning of a movement. Suitably abashed, the JCS has apparently agreed that an entire issue will be devoted to responses to Honderich, some time in the summer.

The least we can do, then, is to have a further look at what these Radical Externalists are saying, and Manzotti’s paper seems a good place to start.

Linespace

The distinctive feature of Manzotti’s theory is that he takes a process-based view. Things don’t exist, in his eyes, they take place. Like many others, he thinks we are to some extent captives of the philosophical outlook adopted four or five hundred years ago, but instead of Descartes getting all the blame, as is usual in these cases, he attributes the main guilt to Galileo (though of course Descartes does not escape unreproved altogether). Galileo, he says, adopted a methodology which separated the observer from an observed world of autonomous objects susceptible to measurement and mathematics. Some features of these objects, such as mass, were really out there in the world; others, notably colour, were really only in the observer’s head. This, clearly, was a productive approach: but what Galileo had no business to do was to add an ontological commitment. The fact that considering the observer and the observed separately allowed him to do some interesting sums did not mean that the observer and the observed were really separate.

This mistake, according to Manzotti, led to our disastrously dualistic outlook, the view that perception happens in the head, and all our difficulties with connecting the inner subjective world with the physical reality outside. Manzotti is surely right to want to remove unnecessary intermediaries from our account of perception – what he refers to as the ‘television’ view.

In fact, he says, the mind is identical with everything the subject is conscious of. Instead of talking about the perceived and the perceiver, we should talk about the unifying process of perception, the ‘onphene’ . Our mental life is composed of these onphenes, reaching out far beyond our skulls. Once we adopt this conception of ‘the enlarged mind’, all the difficult problems of consciousness fall away. We don’t have to reconcile qualia with objective reality because they are objective reality; we need no longer puzzle over intentionality, the link between things which mean and things which are meant: the onphene is intentionality.

Linespace

According to Manzotti, perception in some sense constitutes objects. A favourite example is the rainbow. There is, in fact, no vast coloured arch in the sky: it’s only in the act of observation that the rainbow is brought about. As with Honderich, it would be possible to misconstrue this as a radical kind of relativism – your own perceptions are the only reality – but Manzotti’s outlook is much more commonsensical than that.  Rainbows, after all, still have some underlying physical support in the form of  raindrops and sunlight. I fear this is more commonsensical than it really has any right to be. If there’s still an objective physical world underlying and giving rise to the onphenes, I think some of the old problems of the relationship between mental and physical are merely going to be relocated.  If Manzotti wants to embrace his radicalism fully, I think he is bound to adopt an ontology in which there really is nothing but collections of onphenes. He would then be faced with difficult problems of accounting for why the onphenes exist, and how they come to have certain consistencies and commonalities – the kind of regularities which real objects at one end, and observing people at the other, are generally thought to explain.

One of the challenges he faces, of course is how to account for erroneous perceptions. If all my perceptions just are the things perceived, how could I ever suffer from illusions or mistakes? Manzotti offers an account of dreams and memories in which he seeks to preserve the idea that they are, somehow, realities. Memories are just delayed effects of the onphene still doing its stuff – but hang on there: if my mind is identical with the things it is conscious of, how come my mind is here now and the thing remembered is back then? Dreams, on the other hand, recombine elements drawn ultimately from reality. It is a key point for Manzotti that the contents of the mind can only come from the real world – you cannot imagine anything entirely new, such as a new colour. If I dream of my mother wearing Napoleon’s hat, it is my real mother and (by a more obscure process, since I have never seen it) Napoleon’s real hat that are involved. But surely my-mother-in-the-hat is a legitimate single object of perception, not irreducibly dual. What if I dream of a purple cow? It may be, at some remove, a real cow: but where does the purple come from? A particular purple object? Purpleness?

Linespace

Manzotti goes so far as to claim that the coloured spots created by pressing your eyes (or banging your head – don’t try this at home) derive from real colours we have seen. A person who was blind from birth whose eyes were pressed in this way, he thinks, could not experience colour, but would perceive the spots through the sensation of touch (why not smell?). But the weakest of his defences, I think, is the one presented for the case of optical illusions such as the Kanisza triangle (formed by three ‘pac-men’ providing the apparent corners) or illusions of movement. Manzotti introduces the idea of a ‘perceived triangle’ and ‘perceived motion’ as the objects of perception in these cases. Wasn’t this just the sort of thing he was against? And where is the perceived triangle? Not, surely… in the head of the perceiver?

In short, I think there are unresolved problems in Manzotti’s theory. He might well seek to resolve them by becoming less radical about his externalism – but perhaps it would be more interesting to go the other way: cast off from the shores of mere common sense and set up a truly radical onphene metaphysics.

Linespace

Earlier

home

later